Memento
The Struggle to Unify Images (Intuitions) and Words (Concepts):
LeonardÕs Struggle to Grasp World and Self
Dear Students,
Christopher NolanÕs 2000 film Memento – adopted from Jonathan NolanÕs short story Memento Mori – presents a classic detective motif in which the detective seeking justice gradually discovers that he himself is the perpetrator of the crime, the most classic representation of which is SophoclesÕ Oedipus Rex. This classic motif defines, in many respects, the basic theme of the course – What is it to be a human being? – and in what sense are we free in raising it?
The film – ostensibly about anterograde amnesia – presents a complex drama with many twists and turns, welcoming multiple interpretations and viewings, leaving its viewers with a sense of the potential fragmentation of human life and, at the close of the film, with a sense of the radical freedom at work in unifying oneÕs being in the world. The choppy, disjointed, juxtaposition of an ongoing multiplicity of different scenes forces the viewer to, in effect, assume the same position and posture as the protagonist, Leonard, who is likewise trying to make sense – to retain, to bring together, and to unify – a relentless multiplicity of changing, shifting, disjunctive multiplicity of different experiences. Throughout the term, we will return to this movie, viewing it through the conceptual perspectives of different philosophers, in particular our last figure, Nietzsche, whose radical reinterpretation of KantÕs notion of the freedom provides, in my estimation, the most satisfying way of making sense of the images, dialogue, photos, and notations of the movie. For now, however, I want to use our reading on KantÕs theory of knowledge to point out some key elements of the film, and I am going to simplify things drastically, making the film conform in key respects to KantÕs account of what makes experience possible: namely, the synthesis of intuitions and concepts, which is poignantly portrayed in the film as Leonard desperate attempt to synthesize – to combine and unify – images (i.e. intuitions) and words (i.e. concepts).
First and foremost, I want to draw your attention to the essential pairing in the diegetic reality – the scenes and events – of the movie: the pairing of images with words, pictures with descriptions, visual registers with verbal notations. This is KantÕs contrast between ÒintuitionsÓ (sensory content or Òdirect representationsÓ) with Òconcepts (discursive content or Òindirect representationsÓ). Keep the following chart in mind as you read what follows:
KANTÕS DISTINCTION BETWEEN INTUITIONS AND CONCEPTS AS TYPES OF REPRSENTATIONS |
||
Representations (Vorstellungeng)
for KantÕs are ways in which something can be present or placed (stellt) before (vor) a subject. The
subject can take herself as Òplaced beforeÓ something singular, a Òthis,Ó or
Òthat,Ó Òhere,Ó and ÒnowÓ and take it as
an instance of something general, say a stone, house, or garden. |
||
Intuition Anschauung |
What belongs here
folks? |
Concept Begriff |
Sensible Conditions
of representations |
|
Intellectual
Conditions of representations |
Privileged by
Empiricism |
|
Privileged by
Rationalism |
Capacity of
receiving representations |
|
Capacity of
cognizing an object through these representations |
Receptivity of impressions |
|
Spontaneity of
concepts |
Singular
Representation Representation of singularity |
|
General
Representation Representation of generality |
Object is given |
|
Object is thought |
Faculty of
sensibility |
|
Faculty of
understanding |
Faculty of
receptivity |
|
Faculty of
spontaneity |
Affectation |
|
Function |
Direct relation to
object |
|
Indirect relation
to object |
Immediate
presentation |
|
Mediate
re-presentation |
That through which
something is given |
|
That through which
something is thought |
Refers immediately
to an object |
|
Refers to an object
mediately or through a characteristic or maker |
Sensible/sensory |
|
Intellectual/Cognitive |
Prior to thought |
|
Attendant upon or
to intuitions |
Experiential
Activity |
|
Discursive Activity |
Singular
representation of an object |
|
General
representation of an object |
Immediately depends
upon the presence of the object |
|
Does not depend
upon the objectÕs immediate
self-presentation |
Function of
Singularity of representations |
|
Functions of Unity
among our representations |
Analogy with Linguistic Functions |
||
The use of language
to refer or pick out something immediately present to one |
|
The use of language
to say something about whatever is referred to |
Singular terms and
directly referential terms |
|
Predicate terms |
Indexical terms
such as ÒThis,Ó Òthat,Ó Òhere,Ó Ònow,Ó Òhe,Ó Òshe,Ó Òit,Ó Òthey,Ó Òthose,Ó
etc. |
|
Natural kinds terms
such as Òwater,Ó Òmammal,Ó Òpine,Ó Òspruce,Ó Òrabbit,Ó etc. |
MementoÕs Depiction of the
Contrast Between Intuitions and Concepts |
||
Photograph |
|
Words, Notations,
or Descriptions (usually alongside the image photographed) |
Image (usually a
Òperspective shotÓ taken from LeonardÕs point of view) |
|
Narration or
Dialogue |
Immediate Sensory
Register (from LeonardÕs
point of view) |
|
Mediated Narration
or Commentary (on LeonardÕs part) |
The film opens with a photograph, an image, what Kant would classify as an Òintuition,Ó a Òdirect representationÓ of something there, and it slowly fades, much as images do after we experience an event, when we try to retain in memory the sensory detail so vivid and immediate in the initial perception. There is almost a visual pun in the film when the photograph, a visual image or what Kant calls an Òintuitive representation,Ó actually fades, reversing the chemical process that develops the Polaroid image, the documentation in image of what just happened. Instead of the linear sequence of prior event followed by the developing clarity and definition of the photographic image, we reverse time and move toward the event, but in doing so, we lose the image, which seems to fade away as we approach the actual event photographed. ItÕs disturbing to see the initial clarity and resolution of the photographic image gradually fade and altogether disappear, leaving us with a tabula rasa, disturbing because it is as if we were losing our access to, or grasp upon, what is shown. WhatÕs truly disturbing, however, is the temporal pairing of this fading or aphanisis – the dissolution or disintegration – with our increasing proximity to what really happened. The filmmaker seems to ask us whether proximity to the real event – the truth that we seek – is necessarily purchased at the prohibitively high cost of the erasure of clarity, the fading of determinacy, the dissolution of solidity. Perhaps Nolan is suggesting here that ÒactualÓ event, the happening that makes its impact upon our person in all its potential traumatic directness, is itself a fiction, a retrospective creation of something that never was, however much our images and words point to, and reach for, it retrospectively. Even at the opening of the film we are left with question: Is our access to reality mediated by our desperate attempts to unify images with descriptions, which, in a terrifying way, fade and dissolve as we approximate the truth itself, the event in all of its presumed unfiltered directness and absolute immediacy? From a Kantian philosophical perspective, the question posed is about the possibility of experience, our access to the world, which is not the question of whether I know or not, but, instead, the much more fundamental question of what experience and knowledge are, what makes our experience possible.
Notice that the photo offers a Òdirect representationÓ of something there, or what was there, and it is composed of colors, shapes, and contours, what Kant calls intuitive presentations. The photograph directly presents the situation; it is not indirect or through a discursive representation such as words and descriptions, which conceive reality in general terms. I want you to equate the photo and the Òpoint of view shotsÓ from LeonardÕs perspective – for example, the recurring image of Teddy – with KantÕs term Òintuition,Ó which are presentations of sensory data – the colors, sights, sounds, tastes, smells, and feels that present themselves whenever we are sentient. Kant speaks about one source of ÒrepresentationsÓ as ÒintuitionsÓ or Òsensibility,Ó understood as our passive capacity to receive, from the objects of the world, the sensory registration of sights, smells, tastes, feels, and sounds, all of which directly give or immediately present the object to us. Kant calls this faculty ÒsensibilityÓ or our Òintuitive receptivity,Ó and it directly presents, as here and now, objects in our midst. In one scene, Leonard closes his eyes, then opens them again, closing off and then receiving again the full spectrum of visual, tactile, and auditory sensory data, which impinges upon him as a passively receptive subject, and he declares, ÒYes, the world is there,Ó which Kant would understand as the flow of sensory data – ÒintuitiveÓ representations – that come whether we will them or not. We can close our eyes, but when we open them, sensory data floods in. This is one source of knowledge or experience for Kant, but alone it is insufficient to make up experience. What else is needed? What other component has to come into play for us to have normal, integrated experiences that allow us to know the world about us? What other type of ÒrepresentationÓ do we need to make Leonard a functioning human being?
Concepts of course, which are depicted in the film by words, notions and descriptions, which offer so many ways of Òconceiving,Ó Òtaking upÓ or Òmaking sense ofÓ the sensory content in the photos, which otherwise cannot figure, as Leonard says, Òas a fact.Ó When we see a photograph with writing alongside it, we have a perfect cinematographic way of understanding KantÕs claim that only a ÒsynthesisÓ or ÒcombinationÓ or ÒunificationÓ of intuitions (sensibility) and concepts (understanding) can add up to a meaningful experience. Every time Leonard has some visual experience or holds a photograph, he talks about it, makes notations about how it should be conceived or interpreted, how it should be linked to other possible sensory experiences, making all of his various notations and descriptions – whether words alongside pictures, voice-off narrative, or diagrams on the wall – into so many Kantian concepts. Kant claims that Òintuitions without concepts are blind; concepts without intuitions are empty.Ó This is beautifully depicted in LeonardÕs struggle to make sense of his current situations, in which he desperately tries to synthesize or combine the right concept – word or description – with the appropriate intuitions, whether his own sensory field or his photos. Said differently, Leonard is actively striving to keep things together, to make sense of things, to adequately conceive of what he sees through his sensory modalities, and this captures KantÕs idea that human experience is an active synthesizing or combing or processing of sensory data.
Notice that, in the absence of concepts – ways of noting, talking about, describing, conceiving or, simply put, making sense of what is directly presented in sensory data – one loses the ability to maintain oneÕs sense of self, oneÕs grasp of who one is. Leonard risks losing his identity when he cannot hold onto a relatively stable and coherent world. Unless Leonard finds the right way of putting the world together, he will not be able to put himself back together. Said differently and all at once, the ability to Òmake senseÓ of the world is exactly the same activity of Òmaking senseÓ of oneself as someone with a past, a present, and a future – that is, a continuous experience of a single, unified world. The continuity of the world and the coherence of the self are the two essential sides of the same coin, which Kant understands as the active – what he calls ÒspontaneousÓ – processing or conceptualizing bring together of sensibility and understanding. Teddy taunts and mocks Leonard numerous times throughout the film for not knowing who he, Leonard, is, precisely because he canÕt keep track of other people and situations, who presumably belong to a single, unified world. When Leonard loses track of his having a past, present, and future, he loses his basic grasp of being a human being. Simply put, consciousness just is a unification of past, present, and future, and without such active grasping or holding on to oneÕs being in time – oneÕs past, oneÕs present, oneÕs future – one risks going out of business as a human being.
Kant addresses this key issue in his claim that forms of human intuition are space and time. What is meant by saying that the forms of intuition are space and time? Whenever we are directly or immediately related to an object – again, take the visual register of TeddyÕs annoying smiling face – it is necessarily at a certain time or place. Whenever we have any sensory presentations, they necessarily have a temporal and a spatial index: in other words, we can always ask when and where they happened, and this is the only way in which objects can be presented to us directly. Different times are necessarily ordered in terms of before, during, or after, just as different places are ordered in terms of a totality of contiguous places. If Leonard loses earlier experiences, he canÕt maintain a single, unified perspective upon his life, and he risks becoming as many selves as he has experiences. Also, his inability to make sense of places in terms of returning to them prevents him from having a single field of actions in the world. He simply does not know where he is because he canÕt retain where he has been. For Kant, the unity and singularity of time and place – one time in which all times figure; one world in which all places have their place – are necessarily constitutive of the unity of the self, what Kant calls Òthe transcendental unity of apperception.Ó What he means by this last, ugly phrase is rather simple and commonsensical: one must be able to hold on to all of oneÕs experiences, and if we cannot carry out that task, one risks going out of business as a unified perspective upon, or viewpoint on, the world.
TIME CONSCIOUSNESS:
TEDDY
You read it off your fucking photo. You
don't know me, you don't even know who
you are.
LEONARD
I'm Leonard Shelby, I'm from San
Francisco and I'm -
TEDDY
(bloody grin)
That's who you were, you don't know who
you are.
LEONARD
Shut your mouth!
TEDDY
Lemme take you down in the basement and
show you what you've become.
In this scene, Teddy right provokes Leonard to understand his past in terms of what he has become, of who he is now and what he is now capable to doing, which is seemingly discontinuous with his former self. Consider another scene when Teddy raises the same basic question of whether Leonard can figure himself out in terms of a retained past, a current situation, and a future end.
TEDDY (cont'd)
You haven't got a clue, have you? You
don't even know who you are?
LEONARD
Yes, I do. I don't have amnesia. I
remember everything about myself up until
the incident. I'm Leonard Shelby, I'm
from San Fran -
TEDDY
That's who you were, Lenny. You don't
know who you are, who you've become since
the incident. You're wandering around,
playing detective... and you don't even
know how long ago it was.
TEDDY
Because you're relying on them alone. You
Don't remember what you've discovered or
how. Your notes might be unreliable.
LEONARD
Memory's unreliable.
Teddy snorts.
LEONARD (cont'd)
No, really. Memory's not perfect. It's
not even that good. Ask the police,
eyewitness testimony is unreliable. The
cops don't catch a killer by sitting
around remembering stuff. They collect
facts, make notes, draw conclusions.
Facts, not memories: that's how you
investigate. I know, it's what I used to
do. Memory can change the shape of a room
or the color of a car. It's an
interpretation, not a record. Memories
can be changed or distorted and they're
irrelevant if you have the facts.
Here, Leonard seems to equate memory with simple images and facts with images for with the appropriate descriptions have been given. Leonard assumes the persona of a detective, one who puts the pieces together, fits images and sensory scenes with descriptions, ways of conceiving such images that transforms them from floating questions marks into solid assertions about the world. LeonardÕs Òfacts,Ó then, are the successful unification or synthesis of image and word, picture and description, intuition and concept, and what he calls his Òsystem,Ó his active cognitive processing of data, is nothing nor less than KantÕs account of the type of activity necessary for humans to have experience and knowledge.